?

Log in

No account? Create an account
Philosophy on LJ
What Is Facticity? 
18th-May-2006 11:08 am
mercury
That Heidegger attempts to philosophize concretely and factically out of his intellectual and wholly factic origin, milieu, and life context is the received wisdom about Heidegger the “existentialist” or Heidegger the “hermeneuticist.” But what does it mean to philosophize factically? The way it is stated, how could one not do so? And assuming it is possible not to philosophize factically, how would one contrast such philosophizing with other forms of philosophizing? Initially, to philosophize factically meant the opposite of philosophizing “theoretically.” But just because the theme of Heidegger’s philosophy shifts from the theoretical knower to the self in its everyday practices, it doesn’t follow that the basic way of philosophizing has changed. After all, the purpose of Being and Time is to grasp and produce a theoretical account of the a priori (necessary and universal) categories of factic life. If philosophizing out of one’s own factic life aims at nothing other than producing a theoretical account of that life, it will not do simply to contrast philosophizing factically with philosophizing theoretically.

Heidegger claims that philosophy, understood as the hermeneutics of facticity, does not attempt to get at theoretical truths about the existence in general of some sort of universal humanity but rather about what “is always as its own [das eigene].” (From Phenomenological Interpretations of Aristotle) Heidegger’s target here is the subject-concept advanced by neo-Kantians like Paul Natorp and Heinrich Rickert: neither an empirical self nor an eternal being but rather a principle, like the Kantian “I think,” which must be able to accompany any of my representations. In contrast to this purely formal condition of knowledge, Heidegger’s factic subject is one that can be otherwise and yet is not simply an empirical subject. (Heidegger is no naturalist.) So the first way we can understand the factic subject is by grasping that it transcends the neo-Kantian dichotomy between a “pure” and an “empirical” subject.

On one interpretation, that the subject is factic means that there is a conditioning ground of the subject that is unavailable to theoretical reflection. Such a ground includes things like history, language, embodiment, gender, and power. What at bottom sustains the subject as a knowing being lies outside of and is unavailable to knowledge, and so we are committed to various forms of historicism, hermeneutics, or aestheticism about knowledge.

But this interpretation makes the fatal mistake of running together two different kinds of facticity. Facticity in the “loose” sense refers to the subject’s situatedness, but facticity in the “strict” sense refers to that aspect of the subject that is unavailable to reflection. For example, some have claimed that, by Heidegger’s lights, sex (whether you’re male or female) is a fact, but gender (masculinity and feminity) is factic. Facticity, therefore, consists in socially constructed self-interpretations. If all knowledge is sustained and grounded in such socially constructed self-interpretations, and if such interpretations can change over time, it means that we can never really have a philosophical account of knowledge. Such an account would be the province of gender theory, sociology, history, etc. But such constructed meanings and are available to reflection and so belong to facticity in the loose sense. We can explore the necessary conditions for fulfilling them in a culture and discover how they hang together with other meanings. That we can never get clear about facticity, and that we can never get clear of facticity, is not true of something like gender or any other socially constructed self-interpretation. But it is true of facticity in the strict sense.

Therefore, to say that the factic subject is historical, linguistic, embodied, social, and so on is not wrong; it’s just irrelevant from Heidegger’s point of view. We can’t say that any of these are the factic ground of the subject (in the strict sense) because all of them are available to phenomenological reflection. If they weren’t available to such reflection, I wouldn’t be able to say anything about them at all. And no exploration of the subject’s history, language, embodiment, sociality, etc., can shed light on the subject’s facticity in the strict sense.

If we’re going to take the facticity of the subject seriously as the ground of the subject, we cannot identify it with any sort of situatedness (facticity in the loose sense). We can’t identify it with the historical, the religious, the natural, or anything of the sort. Facticity is radical otherness lying at the basis of reflection. Reflection must remain incapable of getting to the bottom of what sustains it as a theorizing, philosophizing subject.

Wittgenstein more or less says the same thing:
Man has an impulse to run up against the limits of language. Think, for example, of the astonishment that anything exists. … This running-up against the limits of language is Ethics. (Wittgenstein, “On Heidegger on Being and Dread,” from Heidegger and Modern Philosophy)
The level of facticity is that which Wittgenstein, in the Tractatus, points to as that which lies outside of language. The entirety of the Tractatus is a performance or a way of showing this limit up against which language runs. Likewise, the reason that we cannot identify facticity with anything lying within reflection (such as the historical, flesh, power, embodiment, etc.) is because these are all things that we can inspect by means of phenomenological reflection and talk about. Facticity is what Wittgenstein refers to as the “mystical,” but he also calls it “Ethics.” Heidegger has an almost identical interpretation of the relationship between facticity and ethics. Before turning to why Heidegger thinks there is such a connection, first I want to provide a clearer, more positive account of what facticity actually is.

Most commentators seem to think that facticity is the subject’s historicality. But this is wrong. Heidegger describes facticity as “already” finding oneself in a world “beforehand,” so “the primary existential meaning of facticity lies in the character of ‘having been’ [gewesen sein].” (B&T, H328) This translation of Gewesenheit as ‘having been’ is misleading, since the term doesn’t really name something chronologically prior. Instead it indicates the “apriori perfect” or the perfect tense in an a priori aspect. It is not “that which has been and still is, but that which … is always prior to and beyond our determination.” (Thomas Sheehan, “Heidegger’s New Aspect”) Gewesen - sein is the always already, corresponding with Aristotle’s term “essence,” to ti en enai. It has nothing to do with the process of becoming or what occurred in the past and continues to impact the present. It has to do with Heidegger’s temporal interpretation of the a priori. That something is a priori doesn’t mean that it is true in a timeless realm radically apart from this world. It means that it is there “always already.” In every situation in which we find ourselves, the a priori is always binding. (Heidegger talks about this in length in History of the Concept of Time.) That facticity lies in the character of gewesensein means that it is what I always already am. That’s the opposite of historicism.

Facticity is “not something we can come across by beholding it,” and its ontological significance lies in the formal structure of “being delivered over.” This is why facticity is disclosed in mood. Facticity pertains, therefore, to how things matter to us; not what things matter to us. As revealed in mood “the ‘whence’ and the ‘whither’ of throwness ‘remain in darkness.” (B&T, H134-35) All of our knowledge counts for nothing in the face of this “mood-wise disclosure of ‘the ‘that it is’ of the ‘there’ which, as such, stares us in the face with the inexorability of an enigma.’” (B&T, 175) To acknowledge radical otherness, to acknowledge facticity, means to confront the enigma of being-there. (This term, “enigma,” is one of the most important in all of B&T.) And one particular mood, Angst, has special methodological significance, because in this mood we confront this radical otherness, and we discover the origin of the philosophical project itself.

Angst reveals my facticity in such a way that the world no longer makes any claim on me. The historical and rational normativity belonging to the structure of my everyday practices is shown to be null and void. I don’t doubt that such norms exist; they simply don’t matter to me. What I took to be inevitable is shown in anxiety simply to be factual. In the space created by Angst between me and the historical and rational norms of everyday existence there arises the question of whether what does exist ought to exist. If in the grip of Angst I hear a telephone ring, I do not doubt that the telephone rings; I wonder, in a terrifying way, why anything like that should happen in the first place. Herein lies the connection between philosophy and facticity. Angst demonstrates in Dasein an interest in truth, in the rightness of norms and reasons for things, and this interest is co-extensive with Dasein’s existence as such. Dasein is brought face to face with the choice of taking responsibility for truth or else fleeing it (running headlong into the everyday). But such a choice is a precise description of the project of philosophy itself. (And this also shows why, in his encounter with the same phenomenon, Wittgenstein claims that language (philosophy) runs up against ethics.)

Authentic retrieval of facticity, therefore, is not a meaningless encounter with the void; it has the character of an ethico-existential imperative that calls forth the project of philosophy as an interest in truth. To say that the philosophizing subject is factic means that taking responsibility for truth is an essential aspect of the philosophical project. Authentic retrieval of facticity is a response to my obligation to make myself accountable to myself and others for what I do and say. Various continental philosophers have taken facticity to mean that we have to pursue historicism or relativism of some kind. But read correctly, facticity proves that historicism, aestheticism, relativism, pragmatism, etc., all have to be wrong. Or put more precisely, they’re “inauthentic” forms of philosophy that renege on their responsibility to truth.

(This post closely follows in form and content sections of a draft I have of Steven Crowell’s paper “Facticity and Philosophy” which appears as “Facticity and Transcendental Philosophy” in From Kant to Davidson, put out, I think, by Routledge three years ago.)
Comments 
18th-May-2006 03:22 pm (UTC) - Facticity
and how does it all relate to Colbertian "Truthiness"?
18th-May-2006 03:37 pm (UTC)
Have't got the time to read this now, but how is the From Kant to Davidson book? Sounds interesting.
18th-May-2006 03:41 pm (UTC)
I don't know. That's the only essay I know out of it.
18th-May-2006 04:10 pm (UTC)
Geez...I should have picked up the fact you didn't actually have the book from the phrase you stuck on after the title. Yup, Shane needs sleep...
20th-May-2006 01:45 am (UTC)
Thanks again. This is really fascinating stuff. You've lit a fire under me to get to work on understanding Heidegger.
20th-May-2006 05:51 pm (UTC)
Glad to hear it.
20th-May-2006 08:26 am (UTC)
This is really interesting. I'll probably post a question or two when I have time to re-read.
20th-May-2006 05:53 pm (UTC)
This one didn't come out as well as I wanted it to. I don't think I provided enough of a positive account of what facticity is; I was more successful differentiating it from social constructivism, historicism, gender theory, and the like.

I like the one I wrote after this, the one on ethics and ontology. I highly recommend that one. It came out very well.
18th-May-2014 04:33 pm (UTC)
First of all, this is a wonderful piece. Thank you for writing it.

Now my question:

Are you creating a similarity between 'radical otherness' and facticity? Can you elaborate on what you mean by radical otherness and its similarity to facticity?
19th-May-2014 07:05 pm (UTC)
Thank you for the compliment.

I'm saying that facticity is radical otherness lying at the ground of the totality of projects and possibilities Heidegger designates with Dasein, and that this otherness is radical precisely because it can't be recouped theoretically. From the OP:
Facticity is radical otherness lying at the basis of reflection. Reflection must remain incapable of getting to the bottom of what sustains it as a theorizing, philosophizing subject.
In Heidegger's language, it cannot become the subject of a thematic investigation. Heidegger has various names for this otherness, but the fact that, in his earlier work, it is very close in character to what he calls the phenomenological a prior (see his History of the Concept of Time), is the major clue letting us know he doesn't have in mind historicity, relativism, aestheticism, or other things facticity is often taken to mean.

Edited at 2014-05-19 07:06 pm (UTC)
2nd-Aug-2015 02:15 am (UTC) - Whether what does exist ought to exist...
Your essay is better written than most material I see on Heidegger; I commend you on your clarity at the same time that I feel as though philosophical commentary would benefit from a more standardized terminology, with, as far as possible, an attempt to use the same terms in the same way. Then one would not have to, as you do above, take such care to make the meaning of "facticity" clear to the reader. As far as "taking responsibility for truth" is concerned, can one take such responsibility without defining what one means by truth? When I talk about truth, I am concerned with transcendent truth, a truth that exists beyond time, place, or cultural milieu (or facticity). That would be a necessary inquiry to be carried out before addressing the question of "whether what does exist ought to exist. My 21st Century angst derives from my conviction that much of what now exists ought not to exist because it is inimical to human survival, human sanity, or human hope for a future for our descendants.
2nd-Aug-2015 02:59 am (UTC) - Re: Whether what does exist ought to exist...
I don't know. My impression of this 9 years after the fact is that there's probably not a lot of difference between Heidegger's position and that of negative theology. "Facticity" may not strictly speaking be just another name for "God", but it seems to serve that function. Or to put a finer point on it, facticity is the outward sign—manifest in light of "mood"—that I am not and can never be a self-complete entity, but instead, I'm through-and-through dependent upon a ground of existence which is forever in the process of withdrawing.

Or to say the same thing more straightforwardly, it's simultaneously true that (a) I'm absolutely dependent upon X as the ground of existence, but (b) X is impossible. It can only manifest as a kind of raw "thusness" that freaks me out. So of course "only a god can save us". That would be the intervention of the impossible—which by definition can't happen, so we're beyond saving.

Heidegger is probably a bit less interesting or original than my post made him sound.
2nd-Aug-2015 03:36 am (UTC) - Re: Whether what does exist ought to exist...
I like your expression "a raw 'thusness' that freaks me out." It freaks me out too. Nevertheless, I would not adopt your position b) that X is impossible. Only that at present, it seems impossible.
I think there is no intellectual basis upon which I can say that God either exists or does not exist. As a creature with creaturely limitations (which can not be overcome as long as I remain a creature), I can know only what my capacities permit me to know. What we should understand by now, since it has been discussed from the time of Sophocles' Oedipus to the present moment is that human beings are afflicted by hubris, a trait also described in the Genesis account of the creatures' decision to defy the restriction placed upon that particular tree by their Creator. Why did they do so? For the same reason that Oedipus believed he could escape from the oracle's prediction that he would kill his father and marry his mother--arrogance. (We conceited humans always think we can escape our inherent limits because we reject the idea that there is a Power wiser than we, and more far-seeing.) You may remember that when the conceited Oppenheimer and his peers detonated the a-bomb at the Trinity site, O. recited that famous line from the Baghavad Gita "Now I am become Death, destroyer of worlds," a prediction that is well on its way to becoming factual.
I appreciate your candid remark that Heidegger is less interesting than your post makes him appear.
This page was loaded Nov 24th 2017, 2:26 pm GMT.